Negative campaigning: Difference between revisions

From WikiDotMako
(text from jorge castros blog post)
 
m (Protected "Negative campaigning" ([edit=autoconfirmed] (indefinite) [move=autoconfirmed] (indefinite)))
 
(28 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{notice|This essay has been [http://mako.cc/copyrighteous/20110903-00 published on my blog]. You can read the published version and comment on it there.}}


I often hear criticism of "negative campaigning" in the free software movement. For example, in reply to a [http://mako.cc/copyrighteous/20090109-00.comment blog post I once wrote] about an FSF campaign, several people argued against, "negative campaigning of any sort, in any realm." Drawing an analogy to political [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Smear_campaign smear campaigns], some members of the free software community have taken the position that [http://castrojo.wordpress.com/2009/01/09/badvista-declares-pyrrhic-victory/#comment-745 negative campaigning in general is not useful] and that negativity has no place in our advocacy.


I didn’t take anything personally. I’m not personally offended. Sorry if that wasn’t clear. When I called for a little more respect, I was referring to the second half of your post:
First, it is important to be clear on what we mean by a negative campaigns. I believe that there is a fundamental difference between speaking out against policies or actions and smear campaigns that employ untrue claims, ad hominem attacks, and that attempt to avoid a real conversation about issues. I will categorically condemn the latter form of smear campaigning in campaigns for software freedom or for anything else.


    Like say, harassing people at malls and walking around in HAZMAT suits. I, for one, am expecting a bag of manure light on fire on my front porch.
That said, negativity directed at negativity has had a positive effect in many social movements. I have supported and participated in "negative" campaigns against proprietary software, software patents, DRM, centralized network services, and the firms behind these practices. I've done so because I believe that if one is taking an ethical position, it is justified, and often necessary, to not only speak about the benefits of freedom but against acts of dispossession and disenfranchisement.


I think that’s both an incorrect and a insulting characterization of Defective By Design. In any case, however, I appreciate your follow-up. I think I see what you meant.
In some of the most effective social movements, unambiguously negative messages have been central. Should a campaign for abolishing child labor talk only about how valuable adult workers are to their employers or how happy kids are when they don't work?  Should a campaign trying to abolish land mines talk only about the benefits of bomb-free fields and intact lower limbs?  Should a free speech organization only speak out about the social welfare brought by a free press and never against acts of censorship? These may seem like outlandish comparisons but you can find people writing, only a couple centuries ago, about how slavery should be abolished by arguing in favor of the benefits of paid labor. Even if the economic arguments in favor of paid work are strong, these  arguments seems irrelevant and offensive today.  Whether slavery is more or less efficient is a moot point. Society has rejected it because it is wrong.


In terms of your comments on negative campaigning, I think it’s worth approaching the concept of negative campaigns with a little more nuance. Their is often a blurry line between opposing negative policies and the type of smear campaigns common in politics which I think we both categorically oppose.
We have made important strides toward eliminating injustices like child labor and slavery because activists waged decidedly negative campaigns against them and convinced others to join in opposition. In doing so, activists declared the status quo unconscionable and created an ethical responsibility to find alternatives and to [http://mako.cc/copyrighteous/20101017-00 redefine what was "realistic."] While I will not suggest that the movement for software freedom is comparable in ethical weight to these other causes, I know that the free software mission is similar in kind.


However, if one is taking an ethical position and trying to increase people’s freedom, it seems justified to not only speak about the benefits of the freedom but also against dispossession and disenfranchisement. The alternative is like saying that a campaign for abolishing child labor should only talk about how great a value adult workers are to their employers are or that a campaign trying to abolish land mines should talk about the benefits of two lower limbs. Or that a free speech organization should only speak out about the benefits of a free press and not try to organize opposition to censors.
Of course, if one does not think that user control over technology is an ethical issue but is instead merely a matter of choice, one will probably oppose negative campaigns. It is also possible that a particular negative campaign is tactically unwise in that it is unlikely to reach a large audience, unlikely to change people's minds, or be difficult to carry out successfully. But such campaigns are a bad idea because they are ineffective, not because they are negative. Additionally, a movement that is purely negative and offers no reasonable alternative to the stated ill may also be unlikely to succeed. This is why, for example, I believe it is good that the FSF uses the large majority of its resources in the "positive" role of supporting free software.


You can find people writing a couple hundred years ago about how slavery should be abolished because they are economically inferior to low-wage labor. Maybe they were right, but the ethical arguments are what have taken hold. Whether it’s more or less efficient is moot; we as a society have abolished slavery because we believe it is wrong.
For those that do treat technological empowerment as an ethical ideal, it is both justified and essential to condemn the systematic disempowerment of others through non-free software just as we celebrate the benefits of software freedom. "Negative" campaigns against proprietary software, software patents, and DRM in music have already led our community to important -- if incomplete -- victories. The desire to right wrongs has been a critical part of our movement's success and of many others'. We would be wise not to give it up.
 
Now I’m not trying suggesting that these issues have equal ethical weight with software freedom, but I do believe that the FSF’s mission is similar in kind, if not in ethical clarity and importance. The FSF has always taken the position that software freedom is an ethical issue. As a a result, the FSF believes that it is both justified and essential to not only speak out about the benefits of software freedom but against people who are systematically disempowering people. And, in fact, it is useful to do so. Ask any civil liberties organization and they will tell you that they do better as things get worse. Like it or not, it is this type of “negative campaigning” against bad policies that sustains all of these organizations. And I think that in cases where it’s about taking strong ethical positions, that’s OK.
 
You may not support the FSF’s position that user control over technology is an ethical issue. If you don’t, you will almost certainly come to different conclusions about what are appropriate tactics and strategies for free software’s promotion. I think it’s in the interest of the productive dialog to attempt to wrap our heads around these differences and to try to view the situations from other perspectives before we turn to what can sometimes be nasty and unproductive criticism.

Latest revision as of 19:11, 3 September 2011

Notice icon.png This essay has been published on my blog. You can read the published version and comment on it there.

I often hear criticism of "negative campaigning" in the free software movement. For example, in reply to a blog post I once wrote about an FSF campaign, several people argued against, "negative campaigning of any sort, in any realm." Drawing an analogy to political smear campaigns, some members of the free software community have taken the position that negative campaigning in general is not useful and that negativity has no place in our advocacy.

First, it is important to be clear on what we mean by a negative campaigns. I believe that there is a fundamental difference between speaking out against policies or actions and smear campaigns that employ untrue claims, ad hominem attacks, and that attempt to avoid a real conversation about issues. I will categorically condemn the latter form of smear campaigning in campaigns for software freedom or for anything else.

That said, negativity directed at negativity has had a positive effect in many social movements. I have supported and participated in "negative" campaigns against proprietary software, software patents, DRM, centralized network services, and the firms behind these practices. I've done so because I believe that if one is taking an ethical position, it is justified, and often necessary, to not only speak about the benefits of freedom but against acts of dispossession and disenfranchisement.

In some of the most effective social movements, unambiguously negative messages have been central. Should a campaign for abolishing child labor talk only about how valuable adult workers are to their employers or how happy kids are when they don't work? Should a campaign trying to abolish land mines talk only about the benefits of bomb-free fields and intact lower limbs? Should a free speech organization only speak out about the social welfare brought by a free press and never against acts of censorship? These may seem like outlandish comparisons but you can find people writing, only a couple centuries ago, about how slavery should be abolished by arguing in favor of the benefits of paid labor. Even if the economic arguments in favor of paid work are strong, these arguments seems irrelevant and offensive today. Whether slavery is more or less efficient is a moot point. Society has rejected it because it is wrong.

We have made important strides toward eliminating injustices like child labor and slavery because activists waged decidedly negative campaigns against them and convinced others to join in opposition. In doing so, activists declared the status quo unconscionable and created an ethical responsibility to find alternatives and to redefine what was "realistic." While I will not suggest that the movement for software freedom is comparable in ethical weight to these other causes, I know that the free software mission is similar in kind.

Of course, if one does not think that user control over technology is an ethical issue but is instead merely a matter of choice, one will probably oppose negative campaigns. It is also possible that a particular negative campaign is tactically unwise in that it is unlikely to reach a large audience, unlikely to change people's minds, or be difficult to carry out successfully. But such campaigns are a bad idea because they are ineffective, not because they are negative. Additionally, a movement that is purely negative and offers no reasonable alternative to the stated ill may also be unlikely to succeed. This is why, for example, I believe it is good that the FSF uses the large majority of its resources in the "positive" role of supporting free software.

For those that do treat technological empowerment as an ethical ideal, it is both justified and essential to condemn the systematic disempowerment of others through non-free software just as we celebrate the benefits of software freedom. "Negative" campaigns against proprietary software, software patents, and DRM in music have already led our community to important -- if incomplete -- victories. The desire to right wrongs has been a critical part of our movement's success and of many others'. We would be wise not to give it up.